首页> 外文OA文献 >Experience and morality : Buddhist ethics as moral phenomenology
【2h】

Experience and morality : Buddhist ethics as moral phenomenology

机译:经验与道德:佛教伦理作为道德现象学

代理获取
本网站仅为用户提供外文OA文献查询和代理获取服务,本网站没有原文。下单后我们将采用程序或人工为您竭诚获取高质量的原文,但由于OA文献来源多样且变更频繁,仍可能出现获取不到、文献不完整或与标题不符等情况,如果获取不到我们将提供退款服务。请知悉。

摘要

This dissertation comprises two main sections. The first section, comprising Chapters 2udand 3, addresses the methodological problems with seeking to understand Buddhist ethicsudthrough categorizing it into a Western ethical system. Since Buddhist ethics has often beenudinterpreted as either a type of consequentialism or a type of virtue ethics, Chapter 2 is devoted toudaddressing the problems with a consequentialist reading of Buddhist ethics, and Chapter 3 toudhighlighting the structural differences that inhibit a faithful reading of Buddhist ethics as a typeudof virtue ethics. In the second section, consisting of of Chapters 4 and 5, I argue that whenudBuddhist ethical writings are considered on their own terms, there emerges a recurrent anduddominant emphasis on the phenomenology of moral acts. Chapter 4 draws on Buddhistudpsychological texts to elucidate the Buddhist explanation of the foundational components ofudexperience and the way in which these are ethically significant. Chapter 5 looks at Buddhistudethical texts to demonstrate that mental states are prioritized in ethical discussions and that bothudthe Buddhist moral problem and moral solution pertain to the way we see and experience theudworld.udSince Goodman has argued most extensively that Buddhist ethics is best understood as audkind of universalist consequentialism, Chapter 2 begins with an examination of Goodman’sudmethodology and arguments. Goodman identifies an agent-neutral approach as the centraludcharacteristic of a consequentialist ethical system, the characteristic that differentiates it fromudsystems of virtue ethics, which are agent-relative. He interprets themes within Buddhist textsudsuch as the promotion of self-sacrifice and the dedication of merit as evidence of the agentudneutral approach of a consequentialist ethical system. I aim to demonstrate that these examplesudshould be read as moral instructions for the agent’s motivational state rather than evidenceudsupporting that Buddhist ethics is a type of consequentialism. In doing so, I intend touddemonstrate that Goodman’s methodology of confining the inquiry into Buddhist ethics to itsudcategorization as one of two Western ethical systems based on the criteria of Western ethicaludthought limits the possibility for a comprehensive understanding of Buddhist ethics.udI then turn to arguments made by Goodman, Williams, and Siderits specifically in regardudto Śāntideva. These scholars each contend that Śāntideva’s metaphysical position commits himudto a universalist consequentialist ethics and point to his discussion of the ethical meditativeudpractice of equalizing and exchanging self and other in Chapter 8 of How to Lead an AwakenedudLife as evidence. I will contest the claim that the Buddhist doctrine of selflessness entails theudagent neutrality that characterizes consequentialism. I will argue that Śāntideva’s use of theudmetaphysical doctrine of selflessness within an ethical context does not aim to demonstrate audmoral obligation based on agent neutrality, and thus is not a form of consequentialism. Instead, Iudwill argue that he uses it to effect a psychological shift in the agent for the purposes of moraluddevelopment.udI argue that, in Chapter 8, Śāntideva is simply pointing out the irrationality ofuddistinguishing pains based on their owners, together with the possibility for taking on theudconcerns of others as our own, because of the malleable boundaries of the conception of identity.udI contend that, in this section of his treatise, Śāntideva is instructing the practitioner to harnessudthe powerful psychological forces that already exist within our experience, such as the aversionudto our own pain or attachment to our future selves, and extend their scope through expanding theudconception of self, transforming our experience and moral conduct from one motivated by selfconcernudto one centered on concern for others.udAfter arguing that the emphasis on the mental domain of the agent fatally undermines audconsequentialist interpretation of Buddhist ethics, in Chapter 3, I address the virtue ethicsudinterpretation. While it might seem that an emphasis on the mental states of the agent couldudaccord with a form of virtue ethics, I argue that there are structural differences between the twoudsystems that preclude this classification. It is Keown who offers the most detailed account ofudthis position, so using his arguments I engage in a comparative analysis of the structures of virtueudethics and Buddhist ethics. I identify five critical structural features of virtue ethics and argueudthat they do not characterize Buddhist ethics. I will argue that neither the Buddhist account ofudthe relationship between virtues and nirvana nor the Buddhist explanation of moral choice andudagency are consistent with a virtue ethics.udIn the second section, I begin the inquiry into Buddhist ethical writings on their ownudterms. To argue that moral phenomenology is foundational to Buddhist ethical thought, inudChapter 4, I turn first to the Buddhist psychological treatises of Vasubandhu, Asaṅga, andudBuddhaghosa, highlighting the fundamental mental processes that shape experience with the intention of demonstrating that these Buddhist psychology texts provide the foundation forudunderstanding that the way we construct our experience of the world is ethically significant.udIn Chapter 5, I turn to Mahāyāna Buddhist ethical texts to demonstrate how thisudpsychological foundation is used in these texts in the formulation of a moral phenomenology. Iuduse primarily the works of Āryadeva and Śāntideva; I call attention to the fact that these textsudprioritize mental states in their ethical discussions and present a division of two types of moraludperception: the confused way of seeing the world that is characterized by vice and the accurateudway of seeing the world that characterizes virtue. These texts identify the moral problem withudconfusion about reality, and the moral solution as a transformation of the way we experience theudworld through the cultivation of a metaphysically accurate understanding. In the final stage ofudmaking the case for moral phenomenology as central to Buddhist ethical thought, I turn to theudPrajñāparamitā literature, focusing on the Heart Sūtra and Diamond Cutter Sūtra touddemonstrate that in these sūtras we can find the seeds of the ethical system of Āryadeva andudŚāntideva since they also stress the importance of a transformation of vision as the basis ofudethical activity.
机译:本文主要分为两个部分。第一部分包括第二章,第三章和第三章,通过将佛教伦理 udud分类为西方伦理体系来解决方法论问题。由于佛教伦理常常被 ud解释为一种后果主义或一种德性伦理,因此第二章专门通过对佛教伦理的结果主义解读来解决问题,而第三章则着重强调了抑制伦理道德的结构差异。忠实地阅读佛教伦理,将其作为一种美德伦理。在由第4章和第5章组成的第二部分中,我认为,以佛教徒的道德著作作为自己的术语来考虑时,出现了对道德行为的现象学的反复强调。第四章借鉴佛教 udpsychological文本来阐明佛教对 udexperience的基本组成部分的解释以及这些解释在道德上具有重要意义的方式。第五章研究佛教的道德经文,以证明精神状态在道德讨论中处于优先地位,佛教的道德问题和道德解决方案均与我们看待和体验 udworld的方式有关。 ud自古德曼最广泛地论证了佛教伦理学最好理解为普遍主义结果主义的一种,第二章从对古德曼的思想方法和论证的考察开始。古德曼将代理人中立的方法确定为结果主义伦理制度的中心非特征,这种特征将其与代理人相对的美德伦理 ud系统区别开来。他解释了佛教文本 udd中的主题,例如促进自我牺牲和奉献精神,以此作为结果主义伦理体系的代理 udundular方法的证据。我的目的是证明这些例子应该理解为对代理人的动机状态的道德指导,而不是证明佛教伦理是一种后果论。这样做时,我打算证明古德曼将佛教伦理学的探究仅限于根据西方伦理学的标准将其分类为两个西方伦理学体系之一的方法论,这限制了对佛教伦理学的全面理解的可能性。然后,我转向古德曼,威廉姆斯和西德里斯提出的关于 udtoŚāntideva的论点。这些学者都争辩说,ntāntideva的形而上学地位使他 u003d u200b u200b服从普遍主义的结果​​主义伦理学,并在“如何领导觉醒/ udLife”的第八章中指出了他对平等和交换自我的伦理冥想/ udp实践的讨论。我将质疑佛教的无私学说必然导致结果主义的 udagent中立的主张。我将争辩说,ntāntideva在道德语境中对无私的“超物理”学说的使用并非旨在证明基于代理人中立性的“道德义务”,因此,这不是后果主义的一种形式。取而代之的是,我 udwill辩称他用它来实现代理人的心理转变,以达到道德 uddevelop的目的。 udI争辩说,在第8章中,Śāntideva只是指出了基于其所有者的 udinguing痛苦的非理性。 ,以及由于身份概念的可塑边界,有可能将他人的“担忧”作为我们自己。 udI主张,Śāntideva在其论文的这一部分中正在指示实践者驾驭 ud我们的经验中已经存在的心理力量,例如对自己的痛苦的厌恶或对未来自我的依恋,并通过扩大自我的理解,将我们的经验和道德行为从一种出于自我关注的动机中转化而来,从而扩展了它们的范围 ud在争论中指出,对代理人心理领域的强调致命地破坏了佛教伦理的结果论解释。第三,我讲道德道德 ud解释。尽管似乎强调代理人的心理状态可能符合美德伦理学的一种形式,但我认为,这两种分类体系之间存在结构上的差异,因此无法进行这种分类。基恩(Keown)对这个立场提供了最详细的说明,因此我用他的论点对美德,道德和佛教伦理的结构进行了比较分析。我确定了美德伦理学的五个关键结构特征,并认为它们没有体现佛教伦理学的特征。我要论证的是,佛教徒对美德与必杀技之间关系的解释,或者佛教徒对道德选择和威信的解释与美德伦理学都不相符。,我开始以自己的方式调查佛教伦理著作。为了论证道德现象学是佛教伦理思想的基础,在第4章中,我首先介绍了Vasubandhu,Asaṅga和 udBuddhaghosa的佛教心理学论文,着重介绍了塑造经验的基本心理过程,旨在证明这些佛教徒心理学文献为理解我们构建世界经验的方式具有伦理意义提供了基础。 ud在第5章中,我将探讨Mahāyāna佛教伦理文献,以证明如何在这些文本中运用这种 udpsychological基础来制定道德现象学。我主要使用Āryadeva和Śāntideva的作品;我提请注意以下事实:这些文本在其道德讨论中将精神状态置于优先地位,并提出了两种道德/理解的划分:一种以恶习为特征的迷茫看待世界的方式,另一种是对世界的准确理解。是美德的特征。这些文本确定了对现实感到困惑的道德问题,而道德解决方案则通过对形而上学的准确理解的培养,改变了我们体验世界的方式。在把道德现象学作为佛教伦理思想的核心论证的最后阶段,我转向udPrajñāparamitā文学,着眼于《心经》和《金刚切经》,以证明在这些经文中我们可以找到佛教的种子。 Āryadeva和udŚāntideva的道德体系,因为他们也强调了将视力转变作为 deethical活动的基础的重要性。

著录项

  • 作者

    Aitken DT;

  • 作者单位
  • 年度 2016
  • 总页数
  • 原文格式 PDF
  • 正文语种 en
  • 中图分类

相似文献

  • 外文文献
  • 中文文献
  • 专利

客服邮箱:kefu@zhangqiaokeyan.com

京公网安备:11010802029741号 ICP备案号:京ICP备15016152号-6 六维联合信息科技 (北京) 有限公司©版权所有
  • 客服微信

  • 服务号