首页> 美国卫生研究院文献>Archives of Public Health >Revisiting sequential attributable fractions
【2h】

Revisiting sequential attributable fractions

机译:重新审视顺序归因化分数

代理获取
本网站仅为用户提供外文OA文献查询和代理获取服务,本网站没有原文。下单后我们将采用程序或人工为您竭诚获取高质量的原文,但由于OA文献来源多样且变更频繁,仍可能出现获取不到、文献不完整或与标题不符等情况,如果获取不到我们将提供退款服务。请知悉。

摘要

As has been noted elsewhere, confusion abounds regarding the definition and interpretation of population attributable fractions (PAF) in epidemiology [1]. For instance, in their seminal paper where Eide and Gefeller introduce average and sequential attributable fractions [2], they define the population attributable fraction as ‘the proportion by which a disease prevalence (or incidence) is reduced if the whole population is hypothesized to attain the same risk of disease as the individuals within the lowest exposure category.’ The problem with such a definition is it is non-causal. That is, if individuals in the lowest exposure category do have a lower disease risk, it might not be because of any health benefit attributable to the exposure, but because of spurious correlations or even reverse causation. Taking this kind of logic to the extreme, one could make quite non-sensible conclusions regarding say the cot-death risk attributable to Swiss cheese consumption, or the risk of heart disease attributable to doctor visits. Of course, Eide and Gefeller clearly understand this, and later in the paper mention that ‘if there exists a direct cause-effect relationship between the exposure and the disease, the attributable fraction may be interpreted as the proportion of the diseased that would have been prevented if the exposure was totally eliminated from it’ (note that the use of the word eliminate is convenient but slightly misleading as it refers to a hypothetical population where the risk factor of interest was always absent rather than eliminated at a point in time). They then define this second quantity as the ‘etiologic fraction’, introduced by Miettinen [3]. Incidentally, Robins and Greenland [4] discuss a subtly different metric, more directly interpretable as the proportion of disease caused by a risk factor which they also call an etiologic fraction. More recently, the epidemiological community seems to have settled on Miettinen’s definition ([5, 6]). This seems sensible to us as it does have a direct causal implication (that is, it will only be non-zero if the exposure has some causal effect on disease), and can be estimated in real data, provided we can adequately adjust for confounding [7].
机译:正如其他地方所指出的那样,对流行病学群体遗传分数(PAF)的定义和解释进行了混淆[1]。例如,在它们的精细纸中,在艾德和巨须引入平均和顺序归因的级分[2],它们将群体归因于群体归因分数为“如果整个人口被假设以获得达到疾病患病率(或发病)的比例”与最低曝光类别中的个人相同的疾病风险。“这种定义的问题是非因果。也就是说,如果最低曝光类别中的个体具有较低的疾病风险,则可能不是由于曝光的任何健康益处,而是因为杂散的相关性甚至逆转因果关系。将这种逻辑带到极端,可以对瑞士奶酪消费的婴儿床死亡风险或归因于医生访问的心脏病风险来提出相当不合理的结论。当然,EIDE和Gefeller清楚地了解这一点,后来在论文中提到了“如果暴露和疾病之间存在直接的造成关系,则可能被解释为患病的比例防止曝光完全从它中被淘汰'(请注意,使用这个词消除是方便但略微误导,因为它指的假设群体,其中感兴趣的风险因素总是不存在而不是在时间点消除)。然后,它们将该第二次数量定义为Miettinen介绍的“病因分数”[3]。顺便说一句,罗宾斯和格陵兰岛[4]讨论了巧妙不同的公制,更直接解释为由他们还称之为病因系数的危险因素引起的疾病比例。最近,流行病学社区似乎已经解决了Miettinen的定义([5,6])。这对我们来说似乎很明智,因为它具有直接的因果暗示(即,如果暴露对疾病有一些因果影响,则只能是非零),并且可以在真实数据中估计,所以我们可以充分调整混杂性[7]。

著录项

相似文献

  • 外文文献
  • 中文文献
  • 专利
代理获取

客服邮箱:kefu@zhangqiaokeyan.com

京公网安备:11010802029741号 ICP备案号:京ICP备15016152号-6 六维联合信息科技 (北京) 有限公司©版权所有
  • 客服微信

  • 服务号