首页> 外文学位 >Thinking Nature, 'Pierre Maupertuis and the Charge of Error Against Fermat and Leibniz'.
【24h】

Thinking Nature, 'Pierre Maupertuis and the Charge of Error Against Fermat and Leibniz'.

机译:思想性质,《皮埃尔·莫佩图伊斯和对费马和莱布尼兹的错误指控》。

获取原文
获取原文并翻译 | 示例

摘要

The purpose of this dissertation is to defend Pierre Fermat and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz against the charge of error made against them by Pierre Maupertuis that they errantly applied final causes to physics. This charge came in Maupertuis' 1744 speech to the Paris Academy of Sciences, later published in different versions, entitled Accord Between Different Laws Which at First Seemed Incompatible. It is in this speech that Maupertuis lays claim to one of the most important discoveries in the history of physics and science, The Principle of Least Action. From the date of this speech up until the end of the twentieth century, Maupertuis was credited with this discovery. Fermat discovered least time in optical physics, and Leibniz co-discovered infinitesimal calculus. When the credited discoverer of least action in physics accuses the discoverer of least time in optics and the co-discoverer of infinitesimal calculus of error before and audience of mathematicians, physicists and scientists, it is an event that calls out for investigation.;The idea of final causes in physics is the idea that bodies move for an end purpose. During the early modern period, this challenged the intellectual establishment of the day with the idea of thinking in nature. The question which fueled the research for this dissertation is why such a man would accuse two other prominent intellects with such an unprovable metaphysical assumption. The research for this project started with a study of the positions of all three of these men regarding final causes in physics. The second phase was to research the historical context in which Accord Between Different Laws Which at First Seemed Incompatible was written and delivered. This context included the life of Maupertuis as member of the Paris Academy of Sciences and as later President of the Berlin Academy of Sciences. It also included the workings of three highly competitive, state funded, academies of science in Berlin, London and Paris.;Research showed that no formal positions were held on the subject of final causes by either Maupertuis or Fermat. Only Leibniz demonstrated an established and well thought out position on the subject. Research did reveal the story of an ambitious man in Maupertuis, who made it the fulfillment of his ambition to rise in the ranks of math and science within the academies and establish himself as an intellectual great in European culture. Consequently, the life and career of Maupertuis illustrates the sociological dimension of scientific achievement. Accord Between Different Laws Which at First Seemed Incompatible turned out to be a politically calculated speech delivered for the purpose of career advancement. In 1744, Maupertuis was being considered by the King of Prussia, Frederick the Great, and the leadership of the Berlin Academy of Science for the presidency of that institution. Maupertuis knew this. Therefore, the work must be interpreted in this context. Consequently, the charge of error against Fermat and Leibniz by Maupertuis must be interpreted likewise.;Discovery was made in contextual and Leibnizian research that Maupertuis was aware of Leibniz's idea of action from 1738 on, and knowingly claimed to have discovered a generalized notion of action in physics which was not his. It is the story of ambition clouding human judgment. The Leibnizians attacked Maupertuis on this matter, led by a member of the Berlin Academy named Samuel Konig. In the "Konig Affair", Konig accused Maupertuis of what is essentially plagiarism, and Maupertuis countered with charging Konig with forgery for claiming to have in his possession a letter from Leibniz to Jacob Hermann demonstrating Leibniz's knowledge of least action. Maupertuis buries Konig in legal proceedings, but loses his reputation in the process. During the final stages of the Konig affair, Maupertuis admits to Patrick d'Arcy, a member of the Paris academy, that he had used Leibniz's theory of action. Having lost his effective leadership as President of the Berlin Academy, Maupertuis spends the last years of his life in his native France without ever relinquishing his title and office.;When at first examining the charge of error, the immediate notion is that this is a cause and effect argument. It appears to be an argument about the order of metaphysics before physics. This turns out not to be the case. Maupertuis agrees with Fermat and Leibniz at every turn. The charge is all about career success.
机译:本文的目的是捍卫Pierre Fermat和Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz免受Pierre Maupertuis对他们犯的错误的指控,他们错误地将最终原因应用于物理学。这项指控来自毛培瑞(Maupertuis)1744年在巴黎科学院发表的演讲,后来发表了不同版本,题为《乍看似不相容的不同法律之间的一致》。正是在这句话中,莫珀特瑞斯宣称自己是物理学和科学史上最重要的发现之一,即“最少作用原理”。从发表演讲之日起到20世纪末,莫珀瑞斯(Maupertuis)被认为拥有这一发现。费马发现光学物理学中的时间最少,而莱布尼兹则发现了无穷微积分。当被认为是物理学中最少动作的发现者指责光学上最少时间的发现者和数学家,物理学家和科学家面前以及观众面前的误差无穷小演算的共同发现者时,这是一个需要进行研究的事件。物理学中最终原因的概念是物体运动是出于最终目的。在近代早期,这以自然思考的思想挑战了当今的思想体系。促使本文进行研究的问题是,为什么这样一个人会以如此无法证明的形而上学的假设来指责另外两个杰出的智者。该项目的研究始于研究这三个人在物理学中最终原因的立场。第二阶段是研究历史背景,在该历史背景下,起草并交付了最初看起来不兼容的不同法律之间的协议。在这种情况下,莫珀特瑞斯(Maupertuis)曾担任巴黎科学院院士,后来担任柏林科学院院长。它还包括柏林,伦敦和巴黎的三个竞争激烈,由国家资助的科学院的工作。只有莱布尼兹(Leibniz)在这个问题上表现出了既定和深思熟虑的立场。研究的确揭示了一个有雄心壮志的人在莫珀蒂伊斯(Maupertuis)的故事,他实现了自己的雄心壮志,以提高学院内的数学和科学队伍,并确立自己是欧洲文化领域的知识分子的才能。因此,莫伯瑞大学的生活和事业说明了科学成就的社会学意义。乍看起来似乎不相容的不同法律之间的协议原来是出于职业发展目的而进行的政治演说。 1744年,普鲁士国王腓特烈大帝(Frederick the Great)和柏林科学院院长正考虑将Maupertuis担任该机构的主席。 Maupertuis知道这一点。因此,必须在这种情况下解释作品。因此,必须对毛普图伊斯对费马和莱布尼兹的错误指控进行同样的解释。;在上下文和莱布尼兹主义的研究中发现,毛普图伊斯从1738年就意识到莱布尼兹的行动思想,并据称声称已经发现了广义的行动概念。在物理学上不是他。这是雄心勃勃的故事笼罩着人类的判断力。在由柏林学院一位名叫塞缪尔·科尼格(Samuel Konig)的成员领导的情况下,莱布尼兹主义者就此事袭击了莫珀图伊。在“科尼格事件”中,科尼格指责莫普图伊斯本质上是窃,而莫普图伊斯则以控告科尼格声称拥有莱布尼兹给雅各布·赫尔曼的一封信为由,指控他伪造y品,这证明了莱布尼兹关于最少行动的知识。 Maupertuis在法律诉讼中埋葬了Konig,但在此过程中失去了声誉。在Konig事件的最后阶段,Maupertuis向巴黎学院成员Patrick d'Arcy承认,他曾使用莱布尼兹的行动理论。失去了担任柏林学院院长的有效领导权后,莫佩图伊斯在他的故乡法国度过了他的生命的最后几年,而从未放弃他的头衔和职务。因果论据。这似乎是关于形而上学先于物理学的论证。事实并非如此。毛珀图伊斯动Fer接受Fermat和Leibniz的支持。指控全在于事业成功。

著录项

  • 作者

    Lamborn, Richard.;

  • 作者单位

    University of South Florida.;

  • 授予单位 University of South Florida.;
  • 学科 Philosophy.;Philosophy of Religion.;Philosophy of science.
  • 学位 Ph.D.
  • 年度 2015
  • 页码 192 p.
  • 总页数 192
  • 原文格式 PDF
  • 正文语种 eng
  • 中图分类
  • 关键词

  • 入库时间 2022-08-17 11:52:26

相似文献

  • 外文文献
  • 中文文献
  • 专利
获取原文

客服邮箱:kefu@zhangqiaokeyan.com

京公网安备:11010802029741号 ICP备案号:京ICP备15016152号-6 六维联合信息科技 (北京) 有限公司©版权所有
  • 客服微信

  • 服务号