首页> 外文期刊>The American Journal of Psychology >Reconsidering a Science of Psychology Built on Laws
【24h】

Reconsidering a Science of Psychology Built on Laws

机译:重新考虑以法律为基础的心理学

获取原文
获取原文并翻译 | 示例
获取外文期刊封面目录资料

摘要

The argument presented here is that a nomothetic psychology is both desirable and possible. It is prompted by the observation that although our theories and research are scientific, we have failed to create the coherent science that a nomothetic system could provide. A coherent science, a nomothetic system, would broaden our understanding by enabling us to explain (account for) constituent laws in terms of their relationships to higher-level, collateral, and subsidiary laws. It would be useful because the laws at each level could be traced downward through the structure to empirical evidence; lateral connections within the structure could be the source of hypotheses for further research. In addition, a nomothetic structure would provide an orderliness and integration for psychology, making it more easily comprehended, by student and professional alike. Moreover, the conflicts and incongruities discovered during the effort to construct a nomothetic structure would invite deeper, more precise thought and insightful empirical research to correct them, thus refining the structure and pushing psychology further toward scientific maturity. Construction of a nomothetic structure begins as largely an intellectual exercise. By critically examining the multitude of sources available to us, including our personal experience, and identifying the underlying commonalities, we can begin to formulate abstract behavioral laws. Some of these laws will be banal; everyday life is banal. Some will be interesting but not startlingly so. Some, however, will be quite unexpected, if only because, unstated and unrecognized, they may already be part of how we think about behavior. Together, the banal, the merely interesting, and the surprising constitute the beginning of the science we seek-sketchy at first, perhaps, but becoming clearer as we become more skilled in thinking nomothetically. The long-term goal is a hierarchical structure, the edges of which mesh with the laws of biology and other kindred disciplines, and, within the structure, abstract higher-level laws subsume more concrete lower-level laws. The laws at each level will derive their legitimacy from their genealogical ties to other laws in the hierarchy. Each law will have its appended theories and supporting data; empiricism is the ultimate arbiter of theories and, by inference, of laws. But because laws are descriptions abstracted from observation, they often are not amenable to direct test. Thus, the Law of Self-Interest is less amenable to test than either the Law of Effect or the Law of Maximization, both of which are less amenable to test than their respective explanatory theories. On the other hand, absence of empirical support for the theories does not necessarily invalidate the law they are designed to explain; it simply makes their acceptance more tentative; if another theory can be successfully substituted for the one that has been rejected, the law may be preserved. When substitution does not, or cannot, happen, the law ultimately must be rejected and, if possible, replaced by another law that can survive empirical scrutiny of its theories. If no acceptable lower-level laws can be found, the acceptability of the higher-level laws that subsume it is brought into question. On the other hand, if a theory is empirically supported, the validity of the law that it addresses, though not proven, is made more plausible, and work can begin on yet lower-level laws. For example, the Law of Self-Interest and its subsumed Law of Value Compatibility might yield an even lower-order law to the effect that people are able to identify more easily and more quickly that which they dislike than that which they like. But that is a discussion for another day.
机译:这里提出的论点是,道德心理既可取又可能。观察结果提示,尽管我们的理论和研究是科学的,但我们未能创造出一种代名词系统可以提供的连贯的科学。连贯的科学,称谓系统将使我们能够根据构成法律与更高层的法律,附属法律和附属法律的关系来解释(解释)构成法律,从而扩大我们的理解。这将很有用,因为可以通过结构向下追溯到每个级别的法律以找到经验证据;结构内的横向连接可能是进一步研究的假设来源。另外,名词性结构将为心理学提供有序性和整合性,使其更容易为学生和专业人士所理解。此外,在构建法理结构的过程中发现的冲突和不一致会引起更深入,更精确的思想和有见地的实证研究,以纠正它们,从而完善结构并将心理学进一步推向科学成熟。名词结构的构建很大程度上是一种智力活动。通过批判性地检查可用于我们的多种资源,包括我们的个人经验,并确定潜在的共性,我们可以开始制定抽象的行为法则。其中一些法律将是平庸的;日常生活平淡无奇。有些会很有趣,但并非如此。但是,有些仅仅是因为未声明和未被认可而已是意料之外的,它们可能已经成为我们思考行为的一部分。平庸的,仅是有趣的和令人惊讶的共同构成了我们起初寻求粗略研究的科学的开端,但是随着我们变得更擅长以运动方式思考的能力而变得更加清晰。长期目标是分层结构,其边缘与生物学定律和其他同类学科相吻合,并且在该结构中,抽象的较高层法律包含更具体的较低层法律。每个级别的法律都将从与其他法律的族谱联系中获得合法性。每部法律都有其所附的理论和支持数据;经验主义是理论的最终仲裁者,并且通过推理,是法律的最终仲裁者。但是因为法律是从观察中抽象出来的描述,所以它们通常不适合直接检验。因此,自感兴趣定律比效果定律或最大化定律更不易于检验,这两个定律都不比其各自的解释性理论更易于检验。另一方面,对这些理论缺乏经验支持并不一定会使它们旨在解释的法律无效。它只是使他们的接受更具暂定性;如果可以成功地用另一种理论代替被拒绝的理论,那么该法律就可以得到保留。当替代没有发生或不可能发生时,法律最终必须被拒绝,并且在可能的情况下,用可以经受其理论经验检验的另一条法律代替。如果找不到可接受的较低级法律,则质疑包含该法律的较高级法律的可接受性。另一方面,如果理论支持,则所解决的法律的有效性(尽管没有得到证明)变得更加合理,并且可以从更底层的法律开始。例如,“自利法则”及其包含的“价值相容法则”可能会产生甚至更低阶的法则,从而使人们能够比他们喜欢的东西更容易,更快地识别出自己不喜欢的东西。但这是另一天的讨论。

著录项

相似文献

  • 外文文献
  • 中文文献
  • 专利
获取原文

客服邮箱:kefu@zhangqiaokeyan.com

京公网安备:11010802029741号 ICP备案号:京ICP备15016152号-6 六维联合信息科技 (北京) 有限公司©版权所有
  • 客服微信

  • 服务号