首页> 外文期刊>Frontiers in Neuroscience >Commentary: Utility-free heuristic models of two-option choice can mimic predictions of utility-stage models under many conditions
【24h】

Commentary: Utility-free heuristic models of two-option choice can mimic predictions of utility-stage models under many conditions

机译:评论:两种选择的无效用启发式模型可以在许多条件下模仿效用阶段模型的预测

获取原文
       

摘要

Many neuroeconomic studies in the past 10 years have reported neural signals encoding the subjective value (or utility) of offered and chosen goods (Padoa-Schioppa, 2011 ; Bartra et al., 2013 ; Clithero and Rangel, 2014 ; but see O'Doherty, 2014 ). The precise mechanisms through which values are compared to make a decision remain unclear and are matter of current research. However, the fact that neurons in the orbitofrontal and ventromedial prefrontal cortices encode the subjective value of offered and chosen goods, taken together with the fact that lesions to these same areas selectively disrupt economic decisions (Camille et al., 2011 ), strongly suggests that economic choices are ultimately based on these value signals (Kable and Glimcher, 2009 ; Rangel and Hare, 2010 ; Padoa-Schioppa, 2011 ). These results are generally viewed as a significant breakthrough compared to standard and behavioral economic theories, where subjective value (or utility) enters as an “as if” concept. In a recent paper, Piantadosi and Hayden ( 2015 ) challenge this understanding.Goods available for choice can generally vary on multiple dimensions (or attributes), and by definition subjective values integrate all the dimensions relevant to the decision. The authors first examine the specific case in which choices are made between two options that depend only on quantity and probability (two parametric dimensions). Building on an argument originally put forth by Tversky ( 1969 ), they show that decisions based on an integrated utility (algorithm 1) cannot be distinguished from decisions based on a utility-free heuristic (algorithm 2). According to this second algorithm, subjects would first identify the attribute with highest variance and then choose according to that attribute alone (dimensional prioritization). This heuristic does not include the computation of any utility. The authors go on to claim that the same argument applies very broadly to binary decisions between goods that vary on two or more dimensions, provided that the dimensions are decomposable into additive functions. In the last part of the paper, they claim that similar arguments apply to neural data and that neural signals previously found to encode subjective value “ may arise artifactually from utility-free heuristic processes. ”The paper is interesting for it highlights one of the challenges in linking a behavioral choice or a neural signal to the computation of subjective values. Importantly, if the algorithm of Piantadosi and Hayden applied as broadly as the authors claim it does, a pillar of neuroeconomics would find itself on shaky ground. However, upon a closer examination it appears clear that the authors greatly overstated their case, and that the domain of decisions to which their utility-free heuristic applies is actually rather limited. In particular, algorithm 2 fails whenever choices are made between qualitatively different (incommensurable) goods. After discussing the specific case in which options depend only on quantity and probability, the authors write: “Moreover, there is nothing special about the fact that these choices involve risk. For example, in a well-known study, subjects choose between two amounts of juice that differ in flavor and quantity (Padoa-Schioppa and Assad, 2006 ). […] It is plausible to assume that in [that study], the utility of each option may be a product of its scalar values along the two dimensions. If so, it is straightforward to create a utility-free algorithm that makes the same choices as the choice model using the same principles” This statement is actually incorrect. Consider a subject choosing between different quantities of apple juice and orange juice. Importantly, flavor is a subjective and complex sensation that cannot be reduced to the sum of simple components (Small, 2012 ; Spence, 2015 ). Thus different flavors are effectively incommensurable commodities. The statement is incorrect because there is no parametric dimension along which two flavors can be assigned a scalar value. Put in a different way, consider decisions between option 1 = [apple flavor, quantity 1] and option 2 = [orange flavor, quantity 2]. If the first dimension was probability instead of flavor, one could say that probability 1 is larger or smaller than probability 2. But one cannot say that apple flavor is larger or smaller than orange flavor: such statement would be meaningless. As a consequence, one cannot compute the variance in the flavor dimension, as required by algorithm 2. The only way to compare apple flavor and orange flavor is to compute their subjective value, which is precisely what Piantadosi and Hayden argue against. Thus, algorithm 2 cannot account for choices as simple as that between an apple and an orange. More generally, algorithm 2 fails whenever choices are made between incommensurable goods.Algorithm 2 also fails in simple cases where goods vary only on parametric dimensions. For example, consider the choice be
机译:在过去的十年中,许多神经经济学研究已经报道了编码所提供和选择的商品的主观价值(或效用)的神经信号(Padoa-Schioppa,2011; Bartra等,2013; Clithero和Rangel,2014;但请参见O'Doherty ,2014年)。比较值以做出决策的精确机制仍不清楚,这是当前研究的问题。然而,眼眶额叶和腹膜前额叶皮层中的神经元编码所提供和选择的商品的主观价值,以及这些区域的病变选择性地破坏经济决策这一事实(Camille等,2011),强烈表明了这一点。经济选择最终取决于这些价值信号(Kable和Glimcher,2009; Rangel和Hare,2010; Padoa-Schioppa,2011)。与标准和行为经济学理论(主观价值(或效用)作为“好像”概念进入)相比,这些结果通常被认为是一项重大突破。在最近的一篇论文中,Piantadosi和Hayden(2015)挑战了这种理解。可供选择的商品通常可以在多个维度(或属性)上变化,并且根据定义,主观价值整合了与决策相关的所有维度。作者首先研究了在仅依赖于数量和概率(两个参数维度)的两个选项之间做出选择的特定情况。他们以特维尔斯基(Tversky,1969)最初提出的观点为基础,表明基于综合效用(算法1)的决策无法与基于无效用启发式算法(算法2)的决策区分开。根据第二种算法,受试者将首先识别方差最大的属性,然后根据该属性单独进行选择(维度优先级)。该启发式方法不包括任何效用的计算。作者继续声称,同一论点非常广泛地适用于在两个或多个维度上变化的商品之间的二元决策,只要这些维度可分解为加法函数即可。在本文的最后一部分,他们声称类似的论点适用于神经数据,并且先前发现的编码主观值的神经信号“可能是从无效用的启发式过程中人为地产生的。 “这篇论文很有趣,因为它突出了将行为选择或神经信号与主观值的计算联系起来的挑战之一。重要的是,如果Piantadosi和Hayden的算法像作者声称的那样广泛应用,那么神经经济学的支柱将发现自己处于不稳定状态。但是,仔细检查后,显然可以看出作者大大夸大了他们的案子,而其无效用启发式方法适用的决策领域实际上是相当有限的。特别是,无论何时在质量上不同(不可估量)的商品之间进行选择,算法2都会失败。在讨论了期权仅取决于数量和概率的特定情况之后,作者写道:“此外,这些选择涉及风险这一事实并没有什么特别的。例如,在一项著名的研究中,受试者在两种口味和数量不同的果汁中进行选择(Padoa-Schioppa和Assad,2006年)。 […]可以假设在该研究中,每个选项的效用可能是其沿两个维度的标量值的乘积。如果是这样,那么创建一个无效用的算法就很容易了,该算法使用相同的原理与选择模型进行相同的选择。考虑一个主题,在不同数量的苹果汁和橙汁之间进行选择。重要的是,风味是一种主观和复杂的感觉,不能减少到简单成分的总和(Small,2012; Spence,2015)。因此,不同的口味实际上是不可估量的商品。该陈述式是错误的,因为没有参数值维可沿其分配两个标量值。换句话说,考虑选项1 = [苹果味,数量1]和选项2 = [橙味,数量2]之间的决策。如果第一维是概率而不是风味,则可以说概率1大于或小于概率2。但是不能说苹果风味大于或小于橙味:这种说法将毫无意义。结果,无法按照算法2的要求来计算风味尺寸的方差。比较苹果风味和橙味的唯一方法是计算其主观价值,这正是Piantadosi和Hayden所反对的。因此,算法2无法像苹果和橙子那样简单地做出选择。更普遍的是,算法2每当在不可估量的商品之间做出选择时都会失败。算法2在商品仅在参数维度上发生变化的简单情况下也会失败。例如,考虑选择是

著录项

相似文献

  • 外文文献
  • 中文文献
  • 专利
获取原文

客服邮箱:kefu@zhangqiaokeyan.com

京公网安备:11010802029741号 ICP备案号:京ICP备15016152号-6 六维联合信息科技 (北京) 有限公司©版权所有
  • 客服微信

  • 服务号