首页> 外文学位 >Form, harmony, and mechanism in Leibniz's philosophy of laws.
【24h】

Form, harmony, and mechanism in Leibniz's philosophy of laws.

机译:莱布尼茨法律哲学的形式,和谐与机制。

获取原文
获取原文并翻译 | 示例

摘要

In this dissertation I develop a sustained treatment of a topic that is neither well-understood nor much discussed, Leibniz's philosophy of laws of nature. Although all suspect that Leibniz endorses a causal powers account of laws, no one has succeeded in explaining his theory in great detail. While all recognize that the laws are closely related to his theory of nature's perfection, no one has clearly shown how Leibniz moves from his general analysis of perfection to his specific claims about the simplicity and explanatory strength of nature's laws. By explaining Leibniz's metaphysics of laws and his account of their relationship to perfection and scientific practice, I make progress toward better understanding a neglected region of Leibniz's philosophy.;I begin by situating Leibniz's project against the background of the Copernican Revolution. I argue that the Copernican Revolution brought about the decline of Aristotelian natural philosophy and the emergence of the mechanical philosophy. It was in this context that Leibniz developed a theory of laws that was designed to be at once Aristotelian and mechanistic. With the Aristotelians, Leibniz believed that any adequate philosophy of nature must include substantial form. With the moderns, however, Leibniz insisted that particular physical occurrences be explained mechanically, not by way of forms.;Having provided the historical context to Leibniz's project, I dedicate my third and fourth chapters to outlining Leibniz's causal powers account of laws and explaining his motivations for endorsing that theory. I argue that Leibniz analyzes the laws of nature as propositions expressing the ways bodies behave in virtue of their powers when operating with God's ordinary concurrence. I establish this claim by showing that this causal powers account is entailed by Leibniz's philosophy of force and that no other analysis is consistent with Leibniz's belief that the laws could be perpetually violated.;In my fifth chapter I investigate the relationship between the laws and nature's perfection. I argue that Leibniz's account of nature's perfection entails that the laws are coextensive with the axioms and theorems of the best deductive system true of nature. My argument begins by explaining Leibniz's harmony theory of perfection, according to which harmony consists in unity in variety. I show that the variety of a system is determined by the degree of change characterizing the system and that the unity of a system is determined by the number of primitive concepts required to comprehend the system. Applying this theory of perfection to nature, I show that the perfection of nature is determined by the extent to which it is explicable in terms of a deductive system that is both empirically adequate and simple. Leibniz regards a theory as simpler than another if fewer primitive concepts are required for its comprehension than is required for the comprehension of its rival. Because nature's perfection is determined by the degree to which a greater amount of its phenomena are comprehensible by fewer primitive concepts, Leibniz is able to justify simplicity as a theoretical virtue on the grounds that in the best possible world nature is as perfect as it could be.;In my final chapter I argue that once the role of primitive concepts in Leibniz's theory of nature's perfection is clarified, it becomes clear why Leibniz regarded all non-mechanistic explanations of natural phenomena as both unintelligible and inconsistent with the perfection of the physical world. I argue that what Leibniz found so objectionable about primitive gravitational power is that it resists full reduction to distinct primitive concepts. Leibniz's insistence that all explanations be reducible to distinct primitive concepts also explains his peculiar views about the proper role of substantial form in natural philosophy. The reason that substantial form can directly explain the laws themselves but not particular physical occurrences is because the former but not the latter admits of full reduction to distinct primitive concepts.
机译:在这篇论文中,我对莱布尼兹的自然法哲学这个既未被充分理解又未被广泛讨论的话题进行了持续的研究。尽管所有人都怀疑莱布尼兹赞同法律的因果关系解释,但是没有人能成功地详细解释他的理论。尽管所有人都认识到法律与他的自然完美理论紧密相关,但没人能清楚地表明莱布尼兹如何从他对完美的一般分析转向对自然法的简单性和解释力的具体主张。通过解释莱布尼兹的法律形而上学以及他对法律与完善性和科学实践的关系的阐述,我朝着更好地理解莱布尼兹哲学的一个被忽视的领域取得了进展。首先,我将莱布尼兹的项目置于哥白尼革命背景下。我认为哥白尼革命导致亚里士多德自然哲学的衰落和机械哲学的出现。正是在这种情况下,莱布尼兹开发了一种法律理论,该理论旨在同时体现亚里士多德主义和机械主义。对于亚里士多德主义者,莱布尼兹认为,任何适当的自然哲学都必须包括实质形式。然而,对于现代人而言,莱布尼兹坚持要用机械的方式而不是形式来解释特定的物理现象。;为莱布尼兹的项目提供了历史背景之后,我将第三章和第四章专门概述莱布尼兹的因果力法则并解释其原因。支持该理论的动机。我认为,莱布尼兹将自然定律分析为命题,表达了身体在接受上帝的普遍同意时凭借其能力行事的方式。我通过证明这种因果关系的解释是由莱布尼兹的武力哲学所引起的,没有其他分析与莱布尼兹关于法律可能被永久违反的信念相一致;在我的第五章中,我研究了法律与自然法则之间的关系。完美。我认为,莱布尼兹对自然完美性的描述意味着法律与自然界最佳演绎系统的公理和定理共同扩展。我的论点从解释莱布尼兹的完美和谐理论开始,根据和谐理论,和谐在于多样性。我表明,系统的多样性是由表征系统的变化程度决定的,而系统的统一性则是由理解系统所需的原始概念的数量决定的。将这种完美理论应用于自然,我证明了自然的完美取决于它在经验上适当且简单的演绎系统可解释的程度。莱布尼兹认为,如果一种理论的理解所需要的原始概念少于其竞争对手的理解所需要的一种理论,那么它就比另一种理论简单。因为自然的完美取决于更少的原始概念可以理解其大量现象的程度,所以莱布尼兹能够以理论上的美德来证明简单性是有道理的,理由是在尽可能最佳的世界中自然是尽可能完美的在我的最后一章中,我辩称,一旦弄清了原始概念在莱布尼兹的自然完美理论中的作用,就清楚了为什么莱布尼兹将自然现象的所有非机械解释都理解为与物理世界的完美不可理解且不一致。 。我认为,莱布尼兹发现原始原始引力如此令人反感的是,它拒绝完全还原成独特的原始概念。莱布尼兹坚持认为所有解释都可简化为截然不同的原始概念,这也解释了他对实质形式在自然哲学中的适当作用的独特见解。实质形式可以直接解释法则而不是特定的物理现象的原因是因为前者而不是后者承认完全归纳为不同的原始概念。

著录项

  • 作者

    Watson, Joshua L.;

  • 作者单位

    Purdue University.;

  • 授予单位 Purdue University.;
  • 学科 Philosophy.;Metaphysics.
  • 学位 Ph.D.
  • 年度 2012
  • 页码 181 p.
  • 总页数 181
  • 原文格式 PDF
  • 正文语种 eng
  • 中图分类
  • 关键词

  • 入库时间 2022-08-17 11:42:35

相似文献

  • 外文文献
  • 中文文献
  • 专利
获取原文

客服邮箱:kefu@zhangqiaokeyan.com

京公网安备:11010802029741号 ICP备案号:京ICP备15016152号-6 六维联合信息科技 (北京) 有限公司©版权所有
  • 客服微信

  • 服务号