首页> 外文期刊>Journal of applied non-classical logics >Foreword: Three-valued logics and their applications
【24h】

Foreword: Three-valued logics and their applications

机译:前言:三值逻辑及其应用

获取原文
获取原文并翻译 | 示例
       

摘要

Three-valued logics belong to a family of nonclassical logics that started to flourish in the 1920s and 1930s, following the work of Lukasiewicz (1920) and earlier insights coming from Frege and Peirce (see Fisch & Turquette, 1966; Frege, 1879, 1892). All of them were prompted by the idea that not all sentences need be true or false, but that some sentences can be indeterminate in truth value. In his pioneering paper, Lukasiewicz (1920) writes: 'Three-valued logic is a system of non-Aristotelian logic, since it assumes that in addition to true and false propositions there also are propositions that are neither true nor false, and hence, that there exists a third logical value'(Borkowski ed., 1970, p. 86). Lukasiewicz himself was led to introduce a third truth value in order to model the notion of possibility, and to formalise Aristotle's insight that contingent sentences about the future can be indeterminate. Before him, Frege had identified two other reasons to think of sentences as neither true nor false. The first concerns sentences in which a proper name in a sentence fails to refer to an existing individual, as in 'Odysseus was set ashore at Ithaca while sound asleep' (Frege, 1892, p. 27). What Frege points out is that 'anyone who seriously took the sentence to be true or false would ascribe to the name "Odysseus" a reference'. By contraposition, the failure of the name to have a reference should imply that the sentence fails to be either true or false. The second kind of case for which Frege thought sentences could be indeterminate concerns sentences involving vague predicates. For a predicate like 'heap of beans', Frege points out that the classical induction principle cannot be applied, 'on account of the indeterminateness of the notion "heap"' (Frege, 1879, p. 62). Frege did not propose a three-valued logic in relation to those observations, but his remarks find an echo in the supervaluationist system proposed by van Fraassen (1966) to account for the semantics of nonreferential singular terms, and used a decade later by others to account for vagueness (Fine, 1975; Kamp, 1976).
机译:在卢卡西维奇(Lukasiewicz,1920)和弗雷格和皮尔斯(Frege and Peirce)的早期见解之后(参见Fisch&Turquette,1966; Frege,1879,1892),三值逻辑属于一类非古典逻辑,它们在1920年代和1930年代开始蓬勃发展。 )。并非所有句子都必须是真还是假,而是某些句子的真值可以不确定,这一点促使了所有人。 Lukasiewicz(1920)在其开创性论文中写道:“三值逻辑是非亚里士多德逻辑的系统,因为它假设除了正确和错误的命题之外,还存在既不正确也不错误的命题,因此,存在第三个逻辑值”(Borkowski编辑,1970,第86页)。卢卡西维奇本人被引荐引入第三个真值,以便为可能性的概念建模,并使阿里斯多德的见解正式化,即关于未来的偶然性句子可以不确定。在他之前,弗雷格(Frege)已经确定了另外两个将句子视为真假的理由。第一个涉及句子,其中句子中的专有名称不能指代现有的个体,如“奥德修斯在睡着的时候在伊萨卡岛上岸”(弗雷格,1892年,第27页)。弗雷格指出的是“认真对待句子是对还是错的任何人都会将“奥德修斯”这个名字归为参考。相反,如果名称没有引用,则意味着该句子为真或假。弗雷格认为句子可能不确定的第二种情况涉及涉及模糊谓词的句子。对于像“豆堆”这样的谓词,弗雷格指出,“由于概念“堆”的不确定性”,不能应用经典归纳原理(Frege,1879,第62页)。弗雷格并未提出与这些观察有关的三值逻辑,但他的言论在范·弗拉森(van Fraassen,1966)提出的超估价主义体系中得到了回响,以解释非指称单数术语的语义,并在十年后被其他人用于解释模糊性(Fine,1975; Kamp,1976)。

著录项

  • 来源
    《Journal of applied non-classical logics》 |2014年第2期|1-11|共11页
  • 作者单位

    Department of Philosophy, University of Navarra, Navarra, Spain;

    Institut Jean-Nicod (CNRS, ENS, EHESS), Ecole Normale Superieure, Paris, France;

    Philosophy Department, University of Connecticut, Connecticut, USA;

    ILLC, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam, The Netherlands;

  • 收录信息
  • 原文格式 PDF
  • 正文语种 eng
  • 中图分类
  • 关键词

  • 入库时间 2022-08-18 02:20:53

相似文献

  • 外文文献
  • 中文文献
  • 专利
获取原文

客服邮箱:kefu@zhangqiaokeyan.com

京公网安备:11010802029741号 ICP备案号:京ICP备15016152号-6 六维联合信息科技 (北京) 有限公司©版权所有
  • 客服微信

  • 服务号